5

I'm interested in theorems which appear to have very few, if any hypotheses. Essentially a search for unexpected regularity or pattern in a relatively unstructured situation.

By "few hypotheses" I mean theorems which start "take any triangle", or "take any three circles". Similarly, the conclusion of the theorem ought to be really surprising. I know this is a little vague, but I've deliberately left it that way.

Perhaps my favourite here is Morley's theorem. This applies to any triangle, but has a very surprising conclusion. Contrast this with Pythagoras' theorem (needs a right angled triangle: too special!) or Viviani's Theorem (needs an equilateral triangle: too special!).

Can you help me gather a collection? I've made a very preliminary start here: http://tube.geogebra.org/book/title/id/2673817

Part of my underlying interest is in the aesthetic, and what professional mathematicians think is "significant", "surprising" or when exceptional cases mean the "take any .... except ..." means the theorem isn't so general after all.

Please don't be shy. I'd love to know what your favourites are. They don't have to be in geometry either.....

Chris Sangwin

Gerry Myerson
  • 39,024
  • 28
    Sorry to welcome you with a vote to close, but this question is too open to interpretation making it "primarily opinion based." Moreover it is "too broad." –  Feb 16 '16 at 23:12
  • 2
    In the Euclidean plane? That's rather special... – Robert Israel Feb 16 '16 at 23:52
  • 10
    I like the question, and so I have posted an answer. Let's focus the question a bit and ask for people to post interesting theorems of the form: Every such-and-such-completely-standard-kind-of-mathematical-object has such-and-such interesting and perhaps surprising property. – Joel David Hamkins Feb 17 '16 at 00:01
  • 6
    A long-standing problem is whether every infinite discrete group is "sofic" (has some sort of well-defined finite approximation, and idea that originated with Gromov). I've heard that Gromov himself argued that there must be a counterexample, since there are no non-trivial theorems that apply to every group. Maybe Joel's answer is a counterexample to this? – Douglas Lind Feb 17 '16 at 00:45
  • Related: http://mathoverflow.net/questions/18100/theorems-with-unexpected-conclusions – Qiaochu Yuan Feb 17 '16 at 01:05
  • 2
    I think this is a question which could attract poor answers but also good ones, and so I think that for now it may as well stay open. – Yemon Choi Feb 17 '16 at 01:05
  • 29
    A difficulty is that hypotheses can be hidden inside terminology. In the "external tangents to three circles" example, if you didn't assume the word "tangent" and had to deal with just lines and circles, you would suddenly have non-trivial hypotheses to state. Similarly, many a complicated theorem is reduced to a few words by the page of definitions that precedes it. – Brendan McKay Feb 17 '16 at 01:27
  • 3
    Ramsey theory and its relatives (density Ramsey theory, Szemeredi regularity lemma, etc.) contain many examples of this type of phenomenon, where almost the only hypothesis is a largeness hypothesis: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ramsey_theory – Terry Tao Feb 17 '16 at 01:51
  • 4
    Also, there may be some overlap with http://mathoverflow.net/questions/5357/theorems-for-nothing-and-the-proofs-for-free – Terry Tao Feb 17 '16 at 02:01
  • Thank you very much indeed, for the interest in the question, and the links to previous similar topics. – Chris Sangwin Feb 17 '16 at 09:26
  • 1
    It seems the structure you want is "Every A is a B", where A has a simple description and B an interesting description. Is this so? You might then be interested in definability results in mathematical logic. Gerhard " Embedding Mathematical Jewels In Filigree" Paseman, 2016.02.17. – Gerhard Paseman Feb 17 '16 at 15:45
  • 1
  • 3
    The trouble with this question is that it hinges on the requirement of a 'surprising' conclusion, which is incredibly subjective. I'm voting to close again; I really think this question is far too broad and subjective to be suitable. – HJRW Feb 18 '16 at 11:26
  • I hate to disagree with @TerryTao, but although Ramsay theory by definition contains many theorems with weak hypotheses, I wonder if any of the conclusions are really surprising? (Of course, the proofs often are, but that's a different matter.) – HJRW Feb 18 '16 at 11:27
  • 2
    I tend to view Ramsey theorems (particularly density Ramsey theorems) as assertions of the "indestructibility" of certain types of patterns. For instance, Szemeredi's theorem tells us that arithmetic progressions are surprisingly indestructible; one has to eliminate 100% of the integers (asymptotically) before one can eradicate arithmetic progressions of arbitrary length. This can be compared with other patterns, such as triples x,y,z with x+y=z, which can be eradicated by removing just 50% of all integers (the even numbers). Why should x+y=2z (3-term APs) be so much more indestructible? – Terry Tao Feb 18 '16 at 18:28
  • In response to Brendan's comment, Rapoport has said that Scholze is the wizard of making complicated definitions and following them up with short, simple proofs of remarkable facts. – PrimeRibeyeDeal Feb 18 '16 at 22:09
  • The first example that came to my mind is: every nontrivial ring has a maximal ideal. – Joe Mar 18 '24 at 14:02

23 Answers23

34

Theorem. Every group has a terminating transfinite automorphism tower.

Start with any group $G$, compute $\text{Aut}(G)$ and $\text{Aut}(\text{Aut}(G))$ and so on, iterating transfinitely, mapping each to the next via inner automorphisms and taking direct limits at limit stages. Eventually, one arrives at a fixed point, a group that is isomorphic to its automorphism group by the natural map.

26

Every natural number can be written as the sum of four integer squares. (As opposed to the case of three integer squares, which requires certain hypothesis.)

Burak
  • 4,135
21

The theorem of Nash and Tognoli says that any compact smooth manifold is diffeomorphic to a nonsingular real algebraic set.

Todd Trimble
  • 52,336
16
  1. There are infinitely many prime numbers.

  2. Every integer is a product of primes, in essentially unique way.

    (Theorems with NO hypotheses:-)

16

Any linear bounded operator on a Hilbert space can be written as linear combination of four unitary operators.

15

Does the fundamental theorem of algebra count?

Take any (non-constant) polynomial. Then it has a zero among the complex numbers. I suppose this was quite surprising once complex numbers were new.

  • 2
    I guess this falls into the category of the theorems of the form "take any ... except ..." since you have to exclude constant polynomials. – Burak Feb 17 '16 at 00:58
  • 6
    any polynomial, even a constant, can be written in the form $a \prod_{i=1}^n (x-\alpha_i)$ for some $n,a,\alpha_1,\dots,\alpha_n$. – Will Sawin Feb 17 '16 at 03:28
  • 4
    @Burak: I interpret non-constant in the same way as three points on a line is not a triangle. The definition of a triangle includes the 'except' part, and one could imagine this being done for polynomial as well... – Per Alexandersson Feb 17 '16 at 13:27
  • Gonna be picky here, but the polynomial has to have complex coefficients, which adds to the hypotheses. – Wojowu Feb 17 '16 at 14:09
  • 7
    Just out of curiosity: why is this the accepted answer? – Todd Trimble Feb 18 '16 at 01:50
  • @ToddTrimble You might wish to contact Prof. Sangwin as a quicker way of explaining the context, mores etc of MO – Yemon Choi Feb 18 '16 at 10:34
  • This example may go against the philosophy of the original question, which sought a "regularity or pattern in a relatively unstructured situation." The complex field is highly structured. If we ask for a "minimal structure" version of the fundamental theorem of algebra, then we get something like Shipman's theorem that if every polynomial with prime degree has a root then the field is algebraically closed. From this perspective, the fundamental theorem of algebra does have "hidden" hypotheses. – Timothy Chow Feb 10 '23 at 22:16
15

The Feit-Thompson theorem. Every group of odd order is solvable.

Timothy Chow
  • 78,129
  • "Odd order" looks like a hypothesis to me. Actually one that is not even within the reach of first order logic (otherwise, the theorem would be true for infinite groups as well, by compactness). – Sebastian Goette Feb 19 '16 at 08:28
  • 7
    "Odd order" is indeed a hypothesis, but the title of the question allows "very few" hypotheses. As for first-order expressibility, I don't think that most mathematicians care much about that. Finiteness hypotheses are routine in mathematics. – Timothy Chow Feb 20 '16 at 03:54
13

Back in 1907-08, William Henry Young (possibly in part, joint work with his wife, Grace Chisholm Young) proved several "nice behavior" results for arbitrary real-valued functions of a real variable.

In Theorem 6 (p. 82) of [1], Young shows that for co-countably many real numbers $c$ we have

$$\liminf_{x \rightarrow c^{-}}f(x) \; = \; \liminf_{x \rightarrow c^{+}}f(x) \; \leq \; f(c) \; \leq \; \limsup_{x \rightarrow c^{-}}f(x) \; = \; \limsup_{x \rightarrow c^{+}}f(x)$$

(Note: There is a typo in the 2nd inequality at the top of p. 82: $f < {\phi}_R$ should be $f > {\phi}_{R}.)$

This implies two countability results that are now well known. The first is that for an arbitrary function, if both the left limit and the right limit exist at each point, then these unilateral limits can disagree for at most countably many points. The second is that a function can have at most countably many removable discontinuities. Incidentally, this second result was rediscovered by the Romanian mathematician Alexandru Froda in the late 1920s, and there is currently a Wikipedia page titled Froda's Theorem that is misleading at best (see Brian S. Thomson's comments here).

At the 1908 International Congress of Mathematicians, Young announced (see the bottom of p. 54 of [2]) that for co-countably many real numbers $c,$ the left cluster set of $f$ at $c$ is equal to the right cluster set of $f$ at $c.$

This result was proved in [3], where Young additionally showed that at each point of the co-countable set the value of the function belongs to the cluster set. Thus, for co-countably many real numbers $c$ we have

$$C^{-}(f,c) \; = \; C^{+}(f,c) \;\; \text{and} \;\; f(c) \in C^{+}(f,c)$$

This is a seemingly much stronger result than Young's 1907 result, since the 1907 result simply says that the endpoints of the unilateral cluster sets can only differ at countably many points, without saying anything about the distribution of the points belonging to these cluster sets.

Definition: Given a function $f: {\mathbb R} \rightarrow {\mathbb R}$ and $c \in {\mathbb R}$, we let $C^{+}(f,c)$ be the set of all extended real numbers $y$ (i.e. $y$ can be $-\infty$ or $+\infty$) such that there exists a sequence $\left\{x_{k}\right\}$ with each $x_k > c$ and $x_{k} \rightarrow c$ and $f(x_k) \rightarrow y.$ In other words, $C^{+}(f,c)$ is the set of all numbers (including $-\infty$ and $+\infty$) that can be obtained as a limit of $f$-values when using some sequence converging to $c$ from the right. The left version, $C^{-}(f,c),$ is defined analogously.

Regarding these results, see also §6 on pp. 344-346 of [4].

Another result for arbitrary real-valued functions of a real variable (it has been extensively generalized in various directions, as a google search will show) was published by Henry Blumberg in 1922, and a discussion of it can be found at the following math overflow question: Every real function has a dense set on which its restriction is continuous.

[1] William Henry Young, On the distinction of right and left at points of discontinuity, Quarterly Journal of Pure and Applied Mathematics 39 (1908), 67-83. [Paper dated June 1907.]

[2] William Henry Young, On some applications of semi-continuous functions, Atti del IV Congresso Internazionale dei Matematici [4th International Congress of Mathematicians] (Rome), Volume 2, 49-60. [Published version of talk given on 8 April 1908.]

[3] William Henry Young, Sulle due funzioni a più valori costituite dai limiti d'una variabile reale a destra e a sinistra di ciascun pun [On the two functions of multiple values that are determined by the left and right limits of a real variable at each point], Atti della Accademia Reale dei Lincei. Rendiconti. Classe di Scienze fisiche, Matematiche e Naturali (5) 17 #9 (1st semestre) (1908), 582-587. [Paper given at session dated 3 May 1908.]

[4] Andrew Michael Bruckner and Brian Sheriff Thomson, Real variable contributions of G. C. Young and W. H. Young, Expositiones Mathematicae 19 #4 (2001), 337-358.

  • 1
    Seems that the link for [2] is broken. Here is the new link: https://www.mathunion.org/fileadmin/ICM/Proceedings/ICM1908.2/ICM1908.2.ocr.pdf – Falrach Feb 09 '23 at 15:18
  • @Falrach: Thanks! (Curiously, I did not know this question was closed. I've cited my answer here many times, but because it's so far away from the question itself, I had not noticed that the question itself was closed.) – Dave L Renfro Feb 10 '23 at 16:01
12

Liouville's theorem: An entire function is either constant or unbounded.

Similarly, there is little Picard's theorem: The image of an entire function is either $\Bbb C$, $\Bbb C$ without a single point or a single point.

Wojowu
  • 27,379
  • IMHO big Picard is even more surprising: Take any analytic function with an essential singularity and any punctured neighborhood thereof, and the function takes on every value in $\mathbb{C}$ infinitely often with at most one exception on that punctured neighborhood. Imagine if that were true in the reals. Every essential singularity would have to look like this. – Kevin Feb 19 '16 at 05:37
12

The graph minor theorem. In every infinite sequence of finite graphs, one is a minor of another.

I think this one is a very good match to the original request for "a search for unexpected regularity or pattern in a relatively unstructured situation." An arbitrary finite graph is one of the most "unstructured" mathematical objects possible, and the graph minor theorem asserts the existence of a highly unexpected regularity in this unstructured setting. In many of the examples (mentioned in other answers) involving very little structure, the proof of the theorem is relatively short, confirming one's expectation that if you don't assume much, then there's not much scope for nontrivial logical consequences. But the proof of the graph minor theorem is extraordinarily complicated and deep.

Timothy Chow
  • 78,129
11

Let G be any finite group. Then the number of conjugacy classes of G is equal to the number of complex irreducible representations of G.

Yemon Choi
  • 25,496
8

For every holomorphic map from the complex plane to the Riemann sphere, and every $R<\arccos(1/3)$ there exists a disk of radius $R$ in the image in which an inverse holomorphic branch exists. (The constant is best possible).

6

Among my favorites, Monsky's theorem: it is not possible to partition a square into an odd number of equal-area triangles.

dxiv
  • 416
  • I'm interesting in this approach to the question: what is it not possible to do? It reminds me of the so-called "Hairy ball theorem": there is no nonvanishing continuous tangent vector field on even-dimensional $n$-spheres. – Chris Sangwin Feb 17 '16 at 09:27
  • @ChrisSangwin See for example Aigner & Ziegler's "Proofs from THE BOOK". In the 5th edition, Monsky's theorem is presented in Chapter 20, "One square and an odd number of triangles". – Zach Teitler Mar 06 '17 at 07:15
5

Dirichlet's Theorem on Diophantine Approximation: For every real irrational $\alpha$ there are infinitely many rationals $p/q$ with $$\left|\alpha-{p\over q}\right|<{1\over q^2}$$

Gerry Myerson
  • 39,024
5

Every (smooth) cubic surface in $\mathbb P^3$ (over an algebraically closed field) contains exactly 27 lines.

and, of course (surely this one needs to top any list of this sort :))

If a, b, c, and n are positive integers with $a^n + b^n = c^n$, then n = 1 or 2.

4

Bertrand's posutlate states that there exists a prime $p$ such that $n<p<2n$ for all $n\in\mathbb{N}$.

In a similar vein, Rosser's theorem gives the bound $p_n\geq n\log n$ for all $n\in\mathbb{N}$, where $p_n$ denotes the $n$'th prime.

3

Greene's theorem

Curtis Greene, Some partitions associated with a partially ordered set, Journal of Combinatorial Theory Series A, Vol.20(1) (1976) pp 69–79, doi:10.1016/0097-3165(76)90078-9

and the Greene-Kleitman theorem

Curtis Greene, Daniel J Kleitman, The structure of sperner $k$-families, Journal of Combinatorial Theory Series A, Vol.20(1) (1976) pp 41–68, doi:10.1016/0097-3165(76)90077-7

are remarkably deep theorems that hold for any finite partially ordered set.

Greene's theorem. Let $P$ be an $n$-element poset. Let $\lambda_1+\cdots+\lambda_k$ be the largest size of a union of $k$ chains of $P$. Let $\mu_1+\cdots+\mu_k$ be the largest size of a union of $k$ antichains. Let $\lambda=(\lambda_1,\lambda_2,\dots)$ and $\mu=(\mu_1,\mu_2,\dots)$. Then $\lambda$ and $\mu$ are conjugate partitions, i.e., they are weakly decreasing, and the Young diagram of $\mu$ is the transpose of that of $\lambda$.

To see the subtlety of this result, there is for instance a nine-element poset with $\lambda=(5,3,1)$, but $P$ is not a union of a 5-element chain and a 3-element chain.

The fact that $\mu_1$ is the number of parts of $\lambda$ is Dilworth's theorem: the size of the largest antichain of $P$ is equal to the least number of chains whose union is $P$.

David Roberts
  • 33,851
  • 2
    Would it be possible to state the theorems (succinctly) instead of providing PDF links? – Joe Silverman Feb 17 '16 at 01:42
  • 1
    I added human-readable references and stable, doi, links to the abstract pages. – David Roberts Feb 17 '16 at 02:24
  • @Joe Silverman: I have done this for Greene's theorem. Later I will do it for the Greene-Kleitman theorem. – Richard Stanley Feb 17 '16 at 02:24
  • And this is also a Jordan form partition for the nilpotent operator $A$, acting on functions $f:P\rightarrow K$ by $(Af)(x)=\sum_{y<x} c_{yx} f(y)$, where $c_{yx}$ are algebraically independent ('generic') elements of the field $K$. – Fedor Petrov Feb 18 '16 at 07:01
3

Every vector space (or module over a division ring) admits a basis (this includes the empty set as a basis for the zero module). Implicit is the axiom of choice, which I don't consider an extra hypothesis.

All bases of a vector space have the same cardinality.

2

You may have a look at the book

"Combinatorial Geometry in the Plane" by Hadwiger, DeBrunner, and Klee.

For example, one of my favorites is Proposition #9:

"If an infinite set of points is such that all points are at integral distances from each other, then all of the points lie on a straight line."

I guess one could argue that there are significant hypotheses here, but the conclusion seems surprisingly strong.

  • 1
    If we stay in the plane (2D), and we let $n\in\mathbb{N}$ be a finite number, for what $n$ can we have $n$ distinct points, not all collinear, such a all distances are integers? Is this obvious? Edit: Ah, I found the answer myself at Math Stack Exchange. – Jeppe Stig Nielsen Feb 18 '16 at 11:30
1

Every bounded analytic function in the unit disk has radial limits almost everywhere.

1

Even more elementary than Morley's theorem is Napoleon's.

Take any triangle, and construct an equilateral triangle on each of its sides. Then their midpoints form an equilateral triangle, too.

I don't know a striking application of the theorem itself. But from the proof, you can also conclude that if the point $D$ inside the triangle $\Delta ABC$ minimises $d(A,\cdot)+d(B,\cdot)+d(C,\cdot)$, then the line segments $AD$, $BD$ and $CD$ meet at angles $\frac{2\pi}3$ (However, here you need an extra assumption that all angles of $\Delta ABC$ are less than $\frac{2\pi}3$, so this does not count for this question).

1

Here is a theorem that Heinrich Freistuhler & I proved in 1998. There is essentially no assumption.

Let $\phi:{\mathbb R}\rightarrow{\mathbb R}$ be a heteroclinic solution of $\phi'=f(\phi)-q$, where $q$ is some constant. By heteroclinic, we mean that the limits $u_\pm=\phi(\pm\infty)$ exist and are finite. Such functions are viscous standing shocks, that is time-independent solutions of the convection-diffusion equation $$(1)\qquad\partial_tu+\partial_xf(u)=\partial_{xx}^2u.$$ Consider now a function $u_0\in\phi+L^1({\mathbb R})$. Let us define $$h:=\int_{\mathbb R}(u_0-\phi)\,dx.$$ Then the (unique) solution $(x,t)$ of (1) with initial data $u_0$ satisfies (unconditional stability of $\phi$) $$\lim_{t\rightarrow+\infty}\|u(\cdot,t)-\phi(\cdot-h)\|_1=0.$$

This statement assumes neither genuine nonlinearity ($f''$ may vanish arbitrarily), nor decay of $u_0-\phi$ at infinity. The drawback is that the convergence can be arbitrarily slow as $t\rightarrow+\infty$.

Denis Serre
  • 51,599
1

Every compact Riemann surface arises from an algebraic plane curve.

roy smith
  • 12,063