7

On Wikipedia, the definition of inertial mass is:

Inertial mass is the mass of an object measured by its resistance to acceleration. And, can be evaluated using $F = ma$, Newton's second law.

And, in the answer of this question, the viewer has also answered in terms of Newton's second law of motion.

However, I think that both these answers are circular in nature, as Newton didn't derive mass $m$ in terms of force $F$ , he derived $F$ in terms of $m$.

Another confusion I have is related to the law of conservation of momentum. I read that it was experimentally found by Newton that momentum is a "conserved" quantity, which led him to define momentum as $p = mv$ (this is the link to one of my questions regarding momentum).

But now, when I again think of this, I wonder how did he calculated "mass". To experimentally find that momentum is conserved, he must be knowing the values of mass $m$. And even if he used a scale or a weighing machine of some sort, how was he able to calculate $m$ from $F$, even when $F$ is not defined yet?

I am asking this question because I am not able to find the explanation to this anywhere. Most people just answer this in terms of $F$, which is circular. Am I making any mistake in thinking this way, I mean is there any other theory that I don't know?

  • Related: http://physics.stackexchange.com/q/70186/2451 and links therein. – Qmechanic Apr 02 '16 at 11:02
  • In Newton's laws both mass and force are defined at the same time. This is how we teach it in high school physics (assuming your teacher is borderline interested and capable of teaching physics) and there is nothing particularly hard about that. There is no need for circular reasoning at any point in time. Newton's laws do not define absolute force and absolute mass, the only relation that is ever needed to perform physics is a proportionality. You only need an absolute unit for both if you want to do metrology, which is not the same thing as physics. – CuriousOne Apr 02 '16 at 14:10
  • 1
    Ultimately, physics is built on observation. We build hypotheses that attempt to explain known phenomena, and test them by making them predict unknown phenomena. But in the end, we're trying to describe reality, not build a new system from scratch - that's exclusive to mathematics. In turn, all physics must have a certain "circular" component - it must all circle back to reality. – Luaan Apr 26 '16 at 08:49

3 Answers3

6

If you rely on Newton's second law, the definition of mass turns out to be circular or very intricate as also the notion of (undefined) force appears therein. A better approach consists of starting from the experimental fact that momentum is conserved. In a very theoretical picture you can deal with as it follows. You have a set of bodies and you already knows that there is a reference frame $I$ such that

all those bodies simultaneously move with constant velocity therein if they are sufficiently far to each other (and sufficiently far form the other bodies in the Universe).

This reference frame is called inertial. Its existence is the first postulate of Newton's mechanics restated here into a more modern view.

Remaining at rest in $I$, another physical fact is the following. It is possible to associate every body with a strictly positive real number $m$ such that, if a pair of bodies are sufficiently close to each other such that their motion shows acceleration in $I$, it turns out that

$$m_1 \mathbf{v}_1(t) + m_2 \mathbf{v}_2(t) = \mathbf{\textrm{constant}} \tag{1}\:.$$

for every $t\in \mathbb R$ and for every value of $\mathbf{v}_j(t)$ -- which are not constant -- the velocities attained in $I$ during the interaction of bodies.

It also turns out that (in classical physics)

(a) $m_i$ only depends on the $i$-th body and not on the other body, say the $j$-th one, which interacts with the former.

(b) If a number of bodies with masses $m_1,\ldots, m_N$ form a unique larger body with mass $M$, then $M= m_1+\ldots + m_N$.

It is worth noticing that (1) can be theoretically exploited to measure the value of masses with respect to the mass of a given reference body, used as unit $m_1=1$. Measuring the velocities of this reference body and the other body at two different times, we have $$\mathbf{v}_1(t) + m_2 \mathbf{v}_2(t) = \mathbf{v}_1(t') + m_2 \mathbf{v}_2(t') \tag{2}$$ and thus $$\mathbf{v}_1(t) - \mathbf{v}_1(t') = m_2 (\mathbf{v}_2(t') - \mathbf{v}_2(t)) \:.$$ as $\mathbf{v}_2(t') - \mathbf{v}_2(t) \neq \mathbf{0}$ for some choice of $t$ and $t'$ (because the bodies accelerate by hypotheses), there is at most one constant $m_2$ satisfying (2). The fact that it exists is very surprising actually!

  • Hi, Valter! Would you mind on my edit? If so, you can rollback :) –  Apr 02 '16 at 10:18
  • Nice answer. But it seems to me that you more or less rely on Newton's laws without referring to them explicitly. All the considerations related to "distances" that you mention are simply a vague way of saying $F = 0$ on every body in the system. – gatsu Apr 02 '16 at 10:19
  • No, I am only relying on physical facts. There is no way to remove the distance. It is a physical fact that interactions switch off at great distance. After all this is physics and it must be based on physical facts which always are a bit vague. I just tried to minimize the circular part of the definitions and stressing the physical facts behind them. The notion of force is very complex and introducing it makes things much more complicated at this stage. – Valter Moretti Apr 02 '16 at 10:20
  • The fact that interactions disappear at large distance is more general and physically fundamental than the fact that forces disappear at great distance. It survives the passage to other more advanced formulations of mechanics, like the Lagrangian or Hamiltonian version. – Valter Moretti Apr 02 '16 at 10:28
  • @ValterMoretti: how do you talk about interaction without talking about forces? I think your answer runs into exactly the same intricate problems you mention if one starts with the Newton's 2nd law. – gatsu Apr 02 '16 at 10:30
  • @ValterMoretti: hmm...well if it so, that the concept of interaction survives (classically) without that of force, then surely you have a way to define it without invoking the force concept (like with scattering cross sections or the likes). This is what is at stake here I thought, defining mass without appealing to the 2nd law but whilst invoking clear and consistent alternative postulates...which are missing in your answer or are simply hinted to. – gatsu Apr 02 '16 at 10:36
  • @gatsu For inastnce Laundau-Liftis' textbook never use the concept of force. There is a formulation of classical mechanics due to Hertz where forces are not used... – Valter Moretti Apr 02 '16 at 11:20
  • To define the notion of mass we only need to determine a reference frame where conservation of momentum holds. This reference frame is physically defined by the inertia principle. There is a e reference system where all sufficiently distant bodies moves with constant velocity. We do not need to describe interactions, this is just a second step. We need only to know that interactions permit the inertia principle stated as above. – Valter Moretti Apr 02 '16 at 11:22
  • You have merely reformulated Newton without adding anything. There is absolutely nothing circular or tricky about Newton. It simply defines the RELATION between mass and force, which are interdependent, thus it defines BOTH at the same time. – CuriousOne Apr 02 '16 at 14:04
  • @ValterMoretti: I don't know how you introduce the inertia principle (and internal frames) without forces...unless it is assumed that there is an absolute frame of reference along the way (as Newton thought). Landau-Lifshitz's books do use the least action principle as their basis for mechanics. But it is not as powerful and general as Newton's laws and much more abstract. Hertz' principle of least curvature is actually a special case of Gauss' one which involves forces... – gatsu Apr 02 '16 at 14:05
  • The physical content of the inertial principle is clear ad it does not need the introduction of forces. If you have a number of bodies $N>1$ you generally cannot fix their motion changing your reference frame as instead happens for $N=1$. However, if the bodies are sufficiently far to each other it happens that there exists a reference frame where simultaneously they all move with constant velocity. This is the fundamental physical hypotheses determining one and thus all inertial frames. – Valter Moretti Apr 02 '16 at 14:20
  • Landau - Liftis' book defines inertial systems as the systems where space is isotropic and homogeneous and time homogeneous. This means, in their formulation, that the Lagrangian of isolated bodies in these reference frame is invariant under the isometry group of the space and under time translations. – Valter Moretti Apr 02 '16 at 14:23
  • However there are many viewpoints on these issues. Mach spent parts of his famous book on this problem. His formulation is similar to mine... – Valter Moretti Apr 02 '16 at 14:25
  • The usual viewpoint is that Newton got it right and that "force" serves a pretty handy function in the world. No need to go without it... unless one is a purist. :-) – CuriousOne Apr 02 '16 at 14:38
1

However, I think that both these answers are circular in nature, as Newton didn't derive mass $m$ in terms of force $F$ , he derived $F$ in terms of $m$.

Newton's 2nd law does not "derive $F$ in terms of $m$"; it states if force acting on the body $\mathbf F$, mass of the body $m$ and acceleration of the body $\mathbf a$ are determined independently, they always obey the relation

$$ \mathbf F=km\mathbf a. $$

where $k$ is a number depending on the choice of units but otherwise constant in all situations. Later, unit of force - Newton - was defined to simplify this into

$$ \mathbf F=m\mathbf a. $$

Neither of the three quantities is defined by the 2nd law, because that would mean there is no law, only a definition.

The inertial mass $m_{inertial}$ though, is defined by the equation

$$ \mathbf F = m_{inertial} \mathbf a. $$

$m_{inertial}$ is not necessarily constant based on this definition; it is possible that it changes values depending on $\mathbf F,\mathbf a$ or other things. However for low enough speeds, $m_{inertial}$ is proportional to $m$.

But now, when I again think of this, I wonder how did he calculated "mass". To experimentally find that momentum is conserved, he must be knowing the values of mass $m$. And even if he used a scale or a weighing machine of some sort, how was he able to calculate $m$ from $F$, even when $F$ is not defined yet?

To determine mass, one does not need to know definition or value of force. It is possible to determine mass of a body as the number that quantifies amount of matter in the body in terms of a standard amount of matter. For example, body made of 2pockets of sand has mass 2 in units of pocket of sand. Or one can measure mass based on deformation of a weighing spring.

  • You are assuming that there exist objects that apply the same force on every body: the springs in your case. These should be stressed to be fundamental theoretical objects of your theory. This is a new (always hidden) crucial postulate I do not like very much. How can you be sure that springs act with the same force on every body? – Valter Moretti Apr 02 '16 at 11:30
  • Springs are not necessary to use the notion of mass, we can use weight based balance or counting. In case we do use springs, we define mass based on deformation of the spring, no forces are used. – Ján Lalinský Apr 02 '16 at 13:44
  • You are however introducing further crucial hidden hypotheses. It is not forbidden obviously, but they should be explicitly stated. Without them the scheme by Newton is circular. – Valter Moretti Apr 02 '16 at 13:47
  • Newton's laws are BOTH: definitions AND a linear relation. Every capable high school physics teacher should be able to teach it that way. Mine certainly could. – CuriousOne Apr 02 '16 at 14:05
  • @CuriousOne thanks for your precious opinion. I do not intend to reply to you any more henceforth. Here and elsewhere. – Valter Moretti Apr 02 '16 at 14:29
  • @ValterMoretti: Every physicist should also be able to stand a tiny bit of criticism without taking it personally. I am sorry to have hurt your feelings, but there really hasn't been anything particularly tricky about Newton for the past 300 years that would require anybody to reformulate it. We know what it does and it does it well. – CuriousOne Apr 02 '16 at 14:36
  • @ValterMoretti, what are some of the hidden hypotheses you mention? I am not sure what you mean. I was not attempting to formulate axiomatic structure of mechanics here. – Ján Lalinský Apr 02 '16 at 16:26
0

My answer leans towards that of Jan Lalinsky. It is not really clear what is the historical status of force with respect to the mass $m$ of an object in the second law. Some say it is tautological and others that is contingent.

Fortunately, we don't need to answer that question here to gain insights into what Newton may have had in mind when talking about masses.

First of all, we need to first acknowledge that Newton put a great deal of effort to make his 3 fundamental axioms (now called Newtons' laws) consistent and closed.

It is also important to appreciate, as I will try to show, that Newton's synthesis was compiling insights from both dynamical observations (from Galileo and Descartes for instance) and static ones that had in fact been going on for ages just for the purpose of trade of goods, architecture etc...

If you read the second law from the english translation of his Principia it basically says that:

Law 2: The alteration of motion is ever proportional to the motive force impressed; and is made in the direction of the right line in which that force is impressed

i.e. in an inertial frame of reference (only frame in which the notion of "motive force impressed" makes sense according to Newton) we have $a \propto F$. Of course, at that stage neither $F$ nor the proportionality factor are known; but if either comes to be known then the other follows.

I think nothing in the 3 laws of Newton's really forces the proportionality factor to be exactly the mass as we know it. In fact, as Jan Lalinsky stated, we just need to name the prefactor "inertial mass" $m_I$ and the combination of Newton's 3 laws will give that the state of motion of the center of (inertial) mass of any system of points in absence of external forces is following a straight line motion at constant speed (which is equivalent to the conservation of total linear momentum...and this is true regardless of the distances between the points in the system).

Such a proposition had already been made by Descartes for instance but he had postulated that the inertial mass would correspond to the volume of the body on the basis that the laws of Nature ought to be explainable with space and time only. This turned out to be incorrect and a new fundamental concept had to enter the arena.

To see this, we can simply acknowledge that Earth is pulling on a object via a downward motive force called weight and with symbol $W$.

Assuming the terrestrial frame is inertial, we can infer that $m_I a = W$.

Now, we can apply, as Newton did, Galileo's observation that

Provided air friction can be neglected, all bodies observed from a terrestrial frame $T$ fall with the same constant acceleration of magnitude $g$ towards the ground

The only possible conclusion is that $W = m_I g$, where $g$ is the same for all bodies.

There is therefore a direct relationship between the weight of an object and its inertial mass. This enables one to measure relative masses via statics experiments by invoking Newton's 2nd law and this is still how masses are measured today.

To me it seems impossible to talk about masses, in the Newtonian context, without invoking statics and gravity. One can do it as I did above by relying on the practical observation from Galileo or by postulating an additional universal law; which is what Newton did with his Universal law of gravity.

This is important because the grand Newton's synthesis makes sense, in practice, only when his three laws are combined with his universal law of gravity. In fact, he tentatively tried to show that if the gravitational mass of an object was not proportional to its inertial mass, then self consistency of his theory would be lost.

gatsu
  • 7,202