From the representation theory of the Lorentz algebra, we know that spinors (objects transforming under the $(\frac{1}{2}, 0)$ and $(0,\frac{1}{2})$ representation), are naturally equipped with a symplectic structure:
To get something invariant (a scalar = an object transforming according to the $(0,0)$ representation) under Lorentz transformations using two spinors $\xi, \chi$, we must use the spinor metric $\epsilon_{ij}$. For example, $ \chi_i \epsilon_{ij} \xi_j $ is a scalar.
In other words, this means that the scalar product of two spinors is antisymmetric:
\begin{align} \chi \cdot \xi &\equiv \chi_i \epsilon_{ij} \xi_j \\ &= \xi_j \epsilon_{ij} \chi_i \\ &= \xi_i \epsilon_{ji} \chi_j \\ &= - \xi_i \epsilon_{ij} \chi_j \equiv - \xi \cdot \chi\\ \end{align} where we used that in index notation we can switch all objects around freely, because, for example, $\xi_k $ is just a number.
Now, fermions are described by spinors. From the observation above, it does not seem like a big surprise that two fermions do anticommute and hence obey Fermi-Dirac statistics.
Why isn't this sufficient as a "proof" of the spin-statistics-theorem?
I've read several explanations for the various approaches to the spin-statistics-theorem, but almost all are extremely complicated and I started wondering why this is the case. It seems that the very basis observation, namely that spin $\frac{1}{2}$ particles automatically anticommute, follows directly from group theory.