So I can confirm that if you are looking at some Minkowski space, $(1, 2, 3, 4)$ is a 4-vector in that space. In addition if you have a particle and you see it having some velocity components $v_{x,y,z}$, there is a 4-vector with components $(0, v_x, v_y, v_z)$, another with components $(1, v_x, v_y, v_z)$, another with components $(2, v_x, v_y, v_z)$ -- one can pick nits here about units but one cannot deny that basically for any numbers $a,b,c,d$ there is some 4-vector in some basis with components $(a,b,c,d)$.
When we say that something “is a 4-vector” we are not speaking of that, per se. I would say, it is a syntactic statement and not a semantic statement. It has to do with the syntax of the expression that you are using to build the thing, and whether that syntax refers to a consistent geometric entity after coördinate transforms.
So for example when you deal with general relativity you will learn that there is a thing called a Christoffel symbol, and it is calculated from certain things about the metric tensor, which is a tensor, but that we proudly tell our students, “The Christoffel symbol $\Gamma^a_{bc}$ is not a tensor.” This is the same as whether something is a vector or is not a vector, it just has more indexes to fuss over.
The thing is, there surely is a tensor which has the components that the Christoffel symbol has. So what we mean when we say that the Christoffel symbol is not a tensor is this:
- You might use different coördinates to describe the space, say transformed by a Lorentz boost.
- In those different coördinates you might calculate a new Christoffel symbol at this point.
- You might also take the tensor that you assembled from the Christoffel symbol and transform it into the new coördinates.
- But, crucially, these two approaches give you two different objects. The answers that you get when you do these two operations are not identical.
Therefore “Christoffel symbol” is something like a title of nobility or something: much like how, if you translate yourself forwards or backwards in time, the title ‘Earl of Grantham’ might refer to a fundamentally different human being; so, too, if you look at the world in a different way, the Christoffel symbol might be embodied by a different fundamental geometric object in your manifold.
The same is true of, say, $(0, v_x, v_y, v_z)$. That is certainly a four-vector that exists in my space, but if I transform this by a Lorentz boost I will in general find some $(a,b,c,d)$ where $a \ne 0$, and then this will not be the exact same vector I assemble if I look at the same particle's new velocity components $v_{x,y,z}'$ and assemble the four-vector $(0, v_x', v_y', v_z'),$ because that first component will be nonzero.
By contrast if I assemble the four-velocity, which we’d say is a four-vector, $$v^\mu = \frac{1}{\sqrt{1 - (v_x^2 + v_y^2 + v_z^2)/c^2}} (c, v_x, v_y, v_z),$$what makes that thing a four-vector is that those two approaches give you the same object: you can use other Lorentz-transformed coördinates and calculate a velocity in those coördinates and assemble this four-vector from those new components, or you can just transform this four-vector, and you will find out that both of these approaches have given the same geometrical object.
In a more pithy phrasing,
A vector is anything that transforms like a vector. A tensor is anything that transforms like a tensor.
This is not circular: we have model examples like position vectors to tell us how such vectors transform, so that “transforms like a vector” is actually an independent criterion by which we can evaluate whether a proposed method of assembling together numbers into a vector really constitutes a vector. So in 2D space, my shopping list whereby I need one apple and two grapefruits can hypothetically be abused to allow me to assemble a ‘vector’ $(1, 2)$ to describe this shopping list, but that shopping list is ‘not a vector’ because if I rotate space by 45 degrees I do not find that I suddenly need $3 \sqrt{1/2}$ apples and $\sqrt{1/2}$ grapefruits.