86

In Newtonian gravity, an infinite volume filled with a uniform distribution of mass would be in perfect equilibrium. At every point, the gravitational forces contributed by masses in one direction would be exactly counterbalanced by those in the opposite direction.

But when Einstein tried to apply General Relativity to possible cosmologies, he found it necessary to include the cosmological constant in order to get a static universe.

In qualitative terms, it seems to me that the gravitational stresses that the masses would impose on the spacetime should all cancel out, and likewise, that the resulting flat spacetime should have no effect on the motion of the masses.

However, the math of the situation is beyond my current skills, so I'm asking how it produces the nonequilibrium condition?

(I realize that such an equilibrium solution might not be stable, and that there are many other very good reasons to believe in an expanding universe, so I'm not trying to promote any alternative theories. I'm just curious about this particular point. )

tparker
  • 47,418
D. Halsey
  • 2,143
  • 7
    Infinite, flat and non-expanding metric is surely a solution to Einstein's equations: Minkowski metric $\eta_{\mu \nu}$ – Avantgarde Sep 23 '18 at 19:16
  • 1
    @Avantgarde: Is it still considered Minkowski space when the mass distribution is included? – D. Halsey Sep 23 '18 at 19:40
  • 16
    @Avantgarde: The OP is asking about a cosmology with a uniform mass distribution. Minkowski space isn't a solution to the Einstein field equations when the stress-energy tensor is nonzero. –  Sep 23 '18 at 19:59
  • 3
    "-1", The premise of the question is wrong. In Newtonian gravity, an infinite volume filled with a uniform distribution of mass would be in perfect equilibrium not true, uniform distribution of matter would not be in equilibrium in Newtonian gravity either. – A.V.S. Sep 25 '18 at 08:18
  • 1
    Warning: non physicist comment here. In the Newtonian situation, I believe the gravitational forces would be undefined, in the same way as $\Sigma_{i=1}^\infty$ (-1)^i$ is undefined. You can make the force be whatever you want in any direction by taking the integrals in the right way. Intuitively you assume you take the limit of the integral over a ball as the radius of the ball goes to infinity, but there's plenty of other equally valid choices. – Carl Sep 26 '18 at 06:49
  • But this was before we knew the universe likely isn't static. Hubble measured expansion of universe after both theories of relativity were published. – mathreadler Sep 26 '18 at 08:09
  • @Carl This is of course completely correct, and the choice of the way you regulate the sum is equivalent to the choice of boundary conditions mentioned in my answer. No matter how you regulate the sum, you will get collapse to a point, though the regulator does impact which point it is. – knzhou Sep 26 '18 at 16:03
  • @mathreadler -It's been my understanding that, because of formalism to which I think the OP might've wanted to get some verbal approximation (& may've gotten it, from Ben Crowell), that Friedmann (of FLRW fame) had shown that GR required any cosmological model based on it to provide for either expansion or contraction. Einstein didn't immediately accept Friedmann's work. – Edouard Aug 23 '21 at 20:23

7 Answers7

91

This is a rather subtle question, which confused even Newton. It is very tempting to think that an initially static Newtonian universe with perfectly uniform mass density will not collapse, because the gravitational force cancels everywhere by symmetry. This is wrong.

Here's an analogous question: suppose a function $f$ obeys $$f''(x) = 1$$ and we want to solve for $f(x)$. Since every point on the real line is the same as every other point, we might think that by symmetry, $$f(x) = \text{constant}.$$ But this is completely wrong, because the second derivative of a constant is zero. And stepping back, the whole question doesn't make any sense, because there isn't enough information. To solve a general differential equation, you need boundary conditions.

One possible boundary condition is that $f(a) = f(-a)$ for some large $a$. That's enough to specify the solution everywhere, as $$f(x) = \frac{x^2}{2} + \text{constant}.$$ But now the translational symmetry has been broken: not every point is equivalent anymore, as we have a minimum at $x = 0$. This is inevitable. You can't solve the differential equation without boundary conditions, and any choice of boundary conditions breaks the symmetry.

Similarly in Newton's infinite universe we have $$\nabla^2 \phi = \rho$$ where $\rho$ is the constant mass density and $\phi$ is the gravitational potential, corresponding to $f$ in the previous example. Just as in that example, we "obviously" have by symmetry $$\phi(x) = \text{constant}$$ which indicates that the force vanishes everywhere. But this is wrong. Without boundary conditions, the subsequent evolution is not defined; it is like asking to solve for $x$ given only that $x$ is an even number. Any set of boundary conditions will break the symmetry and imply collapse.

For example, dropping irrelevant constant shifts, imposing spherical symmetry about the origin gives $\phi = \rho r^2/6$ which implies collapse towards the origin. Imposing spherical symmetry about a point $\mathbf{a}$ gives $\phi = \rho |\mathbf{r} - \mathbf{a}|^2 / 6$ which implies collapse towards $\mathbf{a}$. And imposing translational symmetry in the $x$ and $y$ directions and symmetry over flipping $z$ gives $\phi = \rho z^2/2$, which implies collapse towards the $z$-axis.

So the answer to your question is that both the Newtonian and relativistic universes immediately start to collapse; the symmetry argument does not work in either one, so there is nothing strange to explain.


The reason this point isn't mentioned in most courses is that we often assume the gravitational potential goes to zero at infinity (in Newtonian gravity) or that the metric is asymptotically flat (in relativity). But this boundary condition doesn't work when the mass distribution extends to infinity as well, which leads to the pitfall here. The same point can lead to surprises in electrostatics.

We reasoned above in terms of potentials. A slightly different, but physically equivalent way of coming to the same conclusion is to directly use fields, by integrating the gravitational field due to each mass. In this case, the problem is that the field at any point isn't well-defined because the integrals don't converge. The only way to ensure convergence is to introduce a "regulator", which makes distant masses contribute less by fiat. But any such regulator, by effectively replacing the infinite distribution with a finite one, introduces a set towards which everything collapses; just like the boundary conditions, any regulator breaks the symmetry.

In the end, both the Newtonian and relativistic universes immediately begin to collapse, and in both cases this can be prevented by adding a cosmological constant. In the Newtonian case, this is simply the trivial statement that $\nabla^2 \phi = \rho - \Lambda$ has constant solutions for $\phi$ when $\rho = \Lambda$. However, in both cases the solution is unstable: collapse will begin upon the introduction of any perturbations.

knzhou
  • 101,976
  • 32
    This is a 'frame challenge' answer, pointing out to a flaw in the reasoning in the original question. The frame challenge answers are perfectly ok on stack exchange. – Maciej Sep 24 '18 at 07:33
  • 1
    Comments are not for extended discussion; this conversation has been moved to chat. – ACuriousMind Sep 24 '18 at 15:23
  • But, formally there is a choice of boundary conditions which respects translation symmetry -- namely, periodic boundary conditions where you put the system on a torus. However, $\phi = $ const is still not a solution in that case -- in fact, $\nabla^2 \phi = \rho$ has no solution on the torus. – Dominic Else Sep 26 '18 at 02:14
  • On this issue of divergence of gravitational force in an infinite Newtonian universe, I recommend John Norton's article "The cosmological woes of Newtonian gravitation theory". The debate goes back to Bishop Berkeley and Newton. But one omission in Norton, as I recall, is that Heckmann & Schucking made Newtonian cosmology rigorous. – Colin MacLaurin Sep 26 '18 at 14:46
  • $f(x)=\frac{x^2}2+x$ is also a solution for the boundary condition $f'(\infty)=-f'(-\infty)$. You must specify this condition more rigorously to make the infinities not independent. In particular, the function I proposed satisfies $$\lim\limits_{x\to\infty}\frac{f'(x)}{-f'(-x)}=1,$$ which is one of possible interpretations of your boundary condition. – Ruslan Oct 12 '18 at 16:40
  • @Ruslan Whoops! You're right, fixed. – knzhou Oct 12 '18 at 17:08
  • Not quite. Your fix doesn't change anything. My function still does satisfy $$\lim\limits_{x\to\infty}\frac{f(x)}{f(-x)}=1,$$ which is compatible with your second condition, as does your function, while the functions differ. The infinities on the LHS and the RHS must be tied together in some way, via a limit or somehow, otherwise your boundary conditions don't constrain $f$ well enough. – Ruslan Oct 12 '18 at 19:18
  • @Ruslan I was really thinking of $\lim_{x \to \infty} f(x) = \lim_{x \to \infty} f(-x), not the ratio thing you're doing. – knzhou Oct 12 '18 at 20:43
  • You can't compare infinite limits for equality. I suppose you actually want limit of difference. Otherwise your notation is ambiguous. – Ruslan Oct 12 '18 at 21:21
  • It doesn't quite fit into the comments space, but, on p.296-297 of his book titled "The Inflationary Universe", Guth has an extremely simple explanation of why an infinite universe containing any matter would, under Newtonian gravity, unquestionably collapse. It uses no more than the simplest algebra. (Einstein's well-known regret about having added a cosmological constant to GR, on the other hand, was, per Eisenstaedt, because expansion would've been a result of the theory even without it, and even in an infinite universe: It would've predicted the Hubble expansion!) – Edouard Jan 22 '19 at 16:28
  • Closely related question here. – knzhou Mar 10 '19 at 15:36
  • any choice of boundary conditions breaks the symmetry the symmetry is not broken, it just acts nontrivially on the potential. Just like in GR the specific choice of coordinates does not break the isometries of (say) FRW solution. If diverging potentials are making you uncomfortable, the problem (infininte homogeneous cosmology) could be handled just fine in Newton-Cartan theory. – A.V.S. Jul 11 '19 at 05:06
  • I am not sure to understand the argument about the boundary condition. If you have f''(x) interpreted as the acceleration of a single test mass at a single point, you only need initial conditions $x(0)=x_0$ and $x'(0)=x'_0$ , you do not need to find the solution for the entire set of particles in the universe, so I am not sure why the answer is about boundary conditions at infinity. –  Jun 27 '22 at 17:16
26

The equation governing the curvature of spacetime in general relativity is $$ R_{\mu\nu} - \frac12Rg_{\mu\nu} = \frac{8\pi G}{c^4}T_{\mu\nu} $$ Or, really, it's $16$ equations in one: $\mu$ and $\nu$ can both take values from $0$ to $3$, representing the four components of any given coordinate system, and for each such choice you get a new equation (with the small caveat that it is symmetric in $\mu$ and $\nu$, so really, it's only $10$ distinct equations).

The symbols $R_{\mu\nu}$, $R$, $g_{\mu\nu}$ and $T_{\mu\nu}$ are so-called tensors, which for now you can think of as real-valued functions on spacetime. (The actual values you get will be dependent on your choice of coordinate system, but if you fix one coordinate system for the region you're interested in they do become just functions. $R$ is a single function while the remaining three, again, are collections of $16$ functions: one for each $\mu, \nu$ pair.)

The left-hand side represents the curvature of spacetime. In flat spacetime we have $R_{\mu\nu} = 0$ for any $\mu, \nu$, and we also get $R = 0$, so the left-hand side will be $0$.

The right-hand side is one big constant multiplied by $T_{\mu\nu}$, which represents the energy at each point in space. In a "sensible" coordinate system (where the $0$-component represents time, and the three remaining coordinates represent space), $T_{00}$ will represent the energy density (including mass density; the other components of $T_{\mu\nu}$ represent things like pressure and momentum density). If there is uniform non-zero mass everywhere, then $T_{00}$ will be non-zero. That means that $R_{00} -\frac12Rg_{00}$ will also be non-zero, which means that we do not have flat spacetime as either $R_{00}$ or $R$ must be non-zero.

In order to regain flat spacetime in this case, and allow both $R_{\mu\nu}$ and $R$ to be zero, it is necessary to add a third term to the left-hand side: the cosmological constant $\Lambda$, giving us $$ R_{\mu\nu} - \frac12Rg_{\mu\nu} + \Lambda g_{\mu\nu} = \frac{8\pi G}{c^4}T_{\mu\nu} $$

Arthur
  • 2,858
  • 2
    I think this is the answer that OP is after! –  Sep 24 '18 at 11:21
  • 1
    Maybe this equation assumes a finite universe or some sort of boundary where all mass-energy $T_{\mu \nu}$ is contained. But with infinite universe the above quation would not apply. – John Alexiou Sep 24 '18 at 13:26
  • 1
    @ja72 I thought the Einstein equation (like most differential equations) had just local terms: the curvature of space at any point (which is just a bunch of derivatives) equals some combination of the energy density, pressure and momentum density at that point (which is just a bunch of local measurements). Which part of the equation would care about the global structure of the universe? – Arthur Sep 24 '18 at 13:48
  • 1
    @ja72: the field equations for GR apply in finite and infinite universes. –  Sep 24 '18 at 14:42
  • 2
    That was my point. historically this equation was developed before the Hubble parameter $H$ and the Friedmann equations which do require a "radius" and a finite universe. Maybe the equation above isn't valid for a non-finite universe. – John Alexiou Sep 24 '18 at 14:45
  • 5
    @ja72: the equations above are the field equations of GR. –  Sep 24 '18 at 15:25
  • 2
    @Arthur: you might want to add a couple of final steps. The field equations reduce to $\Lambda g_{\mu\nu} = 8\pi G/c^4,T_{\mu\nu}$, then since spacetime is flat we can pick $g_{\mu\nu} = \mathop{diag}(1,-1,-1,-1)$ globally, and the expression for $T_{\mu\nu}$ follows immediately. (I could edit this in if you want). –  Sep 25 '18 at 20:43
21

Nice question!

Here's a possible statement of the logic in the newtonian case. (1) In newtonian mechanics, we assume that inertial reference frames exist (this is one popular modern way of restating Newton's first law), we assume that such frames are global, and we assume that we can always find such a frame by observing a test particle that is not acted on by any force. (2) In the newtonian homogeneous cosmology, we could assume that the force on a chosen test particle P can be found by some limiting process, and that the result is unique. (This is basically a bogus assumption, but I don't think that ends up being the issue here.) (3) Given that the result is unique, it must be zero by symmetry. (4) By assumptions 1 and 2, P defines an inertial frame, and by assumption 1, that frame can be extended to cover the entire universe. Therefore all other particles in the universe must have zero acceleration relative to P.

In general relativity, assumption 1 fails. Test particles P and Q can both be inertial (i.e., no nongravitational forces act on them), but it can be false that they are not accelerated relative to one another. For example, we can make an FRW cosmology in which, at some initial time, $\dot{a}=0$, but then it will have $\ddot{a}\ne0$ (in order to satisfy the Einstein field equations for a uniform dust). (In this situation, the Einstein field equations can be reduced to the Friedmann equations, one of which is $\ddot{a}/a=-(4\pi/3)\rho$.)

This shows that the newtonian argument (or at least one version of it) fails. It does not prove that there is no other semi-newtonian plausibility argument that explains why an initially static universe collapses. However, I'm not sure what criteria we would be able to agree on as to what constitutes an acceptable semi-newtonian plausibility argument. Some people have developed these semi-newtonian descriptions of cosmology at great length, but to me they appear to lack any logical foundations that would allow one to tell a correct argument from an incorrect one.

  • 9
    I may be missing something, but I feel like this is answering a slightly different question than the OP is asking. This answer seems to be directed to the uniqueness of the solution, whereas I interpret OP's question to be about its existence. – Owen Sep 24 '18 at 04:51
  • On p.296-297 in the 1997 ed. of Guth's great pop-sci book titled "The Inflationary Universe", there's a plain English description that includes a diagram which I (a visual learner) never tire of: It shows how two spheres of exactly the same density, floating in totally empty (i.e., Newtonian absolute) space, would both collapse in exactly the same amount of time, regardless of whatever huge difference might exist between their surface areas. Whether Friedmann was familiar with that argument is something I have to wonder about, although I doubt that he was: Einstein probably wasn't. – Edouard Aug 23 '21 at 20:38
11

Your question is rather deep and the other answers get to the heart of "what's really going on", but I wanted to just step back and clarify something simple which I don't think anyone else has explicitly pointed out yet:

In Newtonian gravity, an infinite volume filled with a uniform distribution of mass would be in perfect equilibrium. At every point, the gravitational forces contributed by masses in one direction would be exactly counterbalanced by those in the opposite direction.

As other people have pointed out, this is incorrect, for rather subtle conceptual reasons involving the nature of the infinite-space limit. But there's an extremely simple way to see mathematically why an uniform mass density $\rho$ cannot produce an identically zero gravitational field ${\bf g} \equiv {\bf 0}$: Gauss's law for gravity says that ${\bf \nabla} \cdot {\bf g} = -4\pi G \rho$, or equivalently $\iint_{\partial V} {\bf g} \cdot d{\bf A} = -4 \pi G\, M_\text{enclosed}$. It's very clear that ${\bf g} \equiv {\bf 0},\ \rho =$ (nonzero constant) does not satisfy these equations.

tparker
  • 47,418
  • 1
    So which directionality would the gravitational force(field) have? – hkBst Sep 25 '18 at 10:33
  • 1
    @hkBst Depends on the boundary conditions, for which there's no unique natural choice. – tparker Sep 25 '18 at 11:50
  • In the test case, wouldn't there be no real way of defining dA? I think you might be able to find that dA is always zero, and therefore the equilibrium could stand even though it's completely meaningless without space coordinates. – elliot svensson Sep 25 '18 at 17:47
  • 2
    The divergence theorem cannot be used in this case, as I've explained here: https://chat.stackexchange.com/rooms/83586/discussion-on-answer-by-knzhou-why-isnt-an-infinite-flat-nonexpanding-univers - The boundary conditions are given by symmetry that the potential is the same in every point (boundary conditions don't need to be at infinity). The potential also is infinite everywhere and thus its derivative is undefined (other than as zero based on the boundary conditions). Therefore the Poisson's equation fails in the infinite case and cannot be used as an argument against symmetry. – safesphere Sep 26 '18 at 00:04
4

In qualitative terms, it seems to me that the gravitational stresses that the masses would impose on the spacetime should all cancel out, and likewise, that the resulting flat spacetime should have no effect on the motion of the masses.

I think there is a subtle misunderstanding here.

In general relativity, a universe uniformly filled with mass (or really with energy) will see all the forces acting on a massive object cancel, as in the Newtonian case. This is due to the symmetries of a uniform universe.

However, this does not mean that the universe is flat.

In Newtonian mechanics, forces cancelling each other implies a motion following a straight line. Then intuitively it seems like an object could definitely not follow a straight line in a curved space time. But here is the catch: in the context of general relativity, the concept of straight line does not make much sense.

To understand why, we must ask ourselves what is a straight line. In Newtonian mechanics it is easy: it is the path followed by an inertial object, i.e. an object on which we can define a reference frame such that this object in this frame seems to be static and affected by no forces.

The principle of equivalence of general relativity, however, tells us that such a frame can in fact be defined for any free-falling object (object only affected by gravitational forces). The trajectories of such objects are called geodesics and that is the best we can do to extend the Newtonian concept of straight line. In other words, in general relativity "straightness" is an effect of reference frame.

Then, not very surprisingly, in a universe where we consider only gravitation, all objects follow geodesics and thus are moving following "generalized straight lines".

What all of that indicates is that considerations on objects' motion do not give us (to my knowledge) any information about the structure of space and time. Unfortunately this answer does not explain the necessity of an expanding universe, just point out the Newtonian argument is limited. The reason is that as far as I know there is no simple intuitive explanation of the reason behind the expansion of the universe.

Kolaru
  • 149
  • 1
    +1 for actually trying to give a "physical" answer, as OP explicitly states that his maths is not that advanced yet. Also, "proving" anything physical by coming from maths (in this case, the comparison of the question with f''(x)=const) seems a bit like a cop-out to me. Normally reasoning should go the other way round (i.e., the universe does not behave as it is because the math tells it so... math is more of a description, not a reason)... – AnoE Sep 25 '18 at 18:42
  • @AnoE The way physics works is (1) look at simple intuitive cases and guess a physical law, (2) turn that physical law into math, (3) use that math to figure out what happens in less intuitive cases. Simple intuitive cases tell you gravity obeys Newton's laws, which is written in math as $\nabla^2 \phi = \rho$, and then I just applied that to the infinite case. – knzhou Sep 27 '18 at 08:58
  • @AnoE I suppose you could ignore and overrule the math whenever it gives a result that conflicts with your gut instinct. You could do that. But physics run under that principle would never have even gotten to Newton's laws in the first place, much less quantum mechanics. The fact is, human intuition is trained on finite sets of meter-sized objects moving at slow speeds. It's not good at dealing with anything else, and human language reflects these constraints. – knzhou Sep 27 '18 at 09:00
  • @AnoE So you might think, why don't we invent a new language that is more precise, that works even in unintuitive cases like infinite universes? We already have. That language is mathematics, and that's why I'm trusting it. – knzhou Sep 27 '18 at 09:01
  • @knzhou, no need to argue, I'm not saying that physics should be done without maths. There is a place for "lay" explanations though. Take books like https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_Elegant_Universe - you can explain a lot without using maths, especially if the one asking mentions that he does not really have maths available... – AnoE Sep 27 '18 at 09:20
  • @AnoE That’s right, but notice that Brian Greene never ever contradicts any mathematical results. Instead, he starts from the math and uses his words to describe what it says. That’s how physics works — there always is math underneath the words. If the words contradict the math, the words are wrong. – knzhou Sep 27 '18 at 09:23
  • @knzhou, ah, I see. Would you mind pointing out where this answer contradicts the math so it can be improved? – AnoE Sep 27 '18 at 12:48
  • @knzhou I think that the point of AnoE is that physicists (espacially theorists) tend to be too eager to use maths, because they have (rightfully) interiorised the assumptions of the theory. However the maths are only as strong as the starting assumptions, so if you did not interiorised them, all the following may seem build over very muddy foundations. I tried to avoid all but the most basic assumptions here, as it feels more rewarding for some (it does for me at least). – Kolaru Sep 28 '18 at 23:10
3

In Principia Newton introduces the Iron Sphere theorem, which says that you can ignore the gravitational effects of a spherically symmetrical distribution of matter outside of a given sphere. This implies that a uniform distribution of matter should collapse to a point. But there's a problem here: Newton thought in terms of absolute space, and so there's no reason it should collapse to one point rather than another.

The idea of gravity 'cancelling out' in a uniform distribution was discussed in correspondence with Richard Bentley, who was very much part of the religious establishment. My impression is that Newton was happy to seem agreeable here. Principia was OK, but he didn't want the Church investigating his other works too closely. The 'cancelling out' argument pushes the problem off to infinity (so it gives God something to do)

It wasn't particularly satisfactory though, and in 1759 Roger Boscovich proposed a repulsive force to keep matter in balance, essentially an early version of the cosmological constant (this was later developed by William Herschel)

For Einstein though it wasn't possible to push the problem off to infinity, since relativity has to be local. Hence the cosmological constant. (But E.A Milne did use a version of the 'cancelling out' argument for his universe which was expanding but disregarded gravity on large scales)

quantropy
  • 387
0

One more perspective: the question is essentially why the solution to the relevant equation of motion doesn't have the same symmetry as the EOM does. This isn't a unique feature of gravity!

EOM symmetries are closure rules for the solution set, not properties of individual solutions; for example, the translational invariance of $f^{\prime\prime}=c$ means that if $f(x)$ is a solution so is $f(x-a)$, not that $f(x)\equiv f(x-a)$. Once boundary conditions specify one solution, neither the conditions nor the solution keeps the EOM symmetry; the former explains the latter.

This is called spontaneous symmetry breaking. Sure, that term usually comes up when a complex scalar's Lagrangian is invariant under phase shifts, but that's a historical accident from when we were thinking about the Higgs field. The principle is general. Here's a much simpler application of it to gravity than in the OP: if you hold up a pen with a fingertip, while one end balances on a table, when you let go it falls in a specific direction. The symmetry has been broken.

J.G.
  • 24,837